Every thing which is able to return to itself is self-subsistent.

For if it returns to itself according to nature, it is perfect in the conversion to itself, and will possess essence from itself. For from every thing to which there is a return according to nature, there is equally a progression according to essence. If, therefore, it imparts well-being to itself, it will likewise undoubtedly impart being to itself, and will be the lord of its own hypostasis or nature. Hence that which is able to revert to itself is self-subsistent.

COMMENTARY

This is the straightforward corollary to the previous proposition. We're still discussing the Henads, the Unities or Gods. These are self-subsistent, meaning they are their own cause, and they return to themselves, because they are themselves the source of their own good. Last time we learned that self-subsistent things are converted, or return, to themselves; this time we learn that things that return to themselves are self-subsistent. This is the process of "epistrophe" or reversion, the third term in the triad Mone-Prohodos-Epistrophe, or Abiding-Proceeding-Returning, which, as we have seen, underlies the whole of Neoplatonic metaphysics. 

Welcome back to the Plotinus read-through! 

Today we're going to look at Ennead 1, Tractate 2, Chapter 5. You can read along here. The previous post in this series is here.


In this chapter, Plotinus is going to continue to discuss purification. And this, if I may be forgiven the vulgarity, is where shit gets real.

So we come to the scope of the purification: that understood, the nature of Likeness becomes clear. Likeness to what Principle? Identity with what God?

The question is substantially this: how far does purification dispel the two orders of passion- anger, desire and the like, with grief and its kin- and in what degree the disengagement from the body is possible.

Our goal in Purification is to totally liberate ourselves from the passions. The passions, now, are all the involuntary movements of the soul by the body. Some are fiery, like anger and lust, others watery, like grief and sorrow. We seek, on this account, to transcend all of them.

As a note to myself, I feel certain that all of this can be profitably compared with the notion of "separating yang from yin" in the internal alchemy and meditative methods of the Quan Zhen (Complete Reality) school of Chinese Taoism. That comparison is going to have to wait until I can get the rest of my library out of storage, though!

Let's go on and see just how far, for Plotinus, this all goes.

Disengagement means simply that the soul withdraws to its own place.

That sounds simple enough. Plotinus now describes what it looks like in practice, and this is important enough that I'm going to break it up into sections.
 

  • It will hold itself above all passions and affections.
  • Necessary pleasures and all the activity of the senses it will employ only for medicament and assuagement lets its work be impeded.
  • Pain it may combat, but, failing the cure, it will bear meekly and ease it by refusing assent to it.
  • All passionate action it will check: the suppression will be complete if that is possible, but at worst the Soul will never itself take fire but will keep the involuntary and uncontrolled outside its own precincts and rare and weak at that.
  • The Soul has nothing to dread, though no doubt the involuntary has some power here too: fear therefore must cease, except insofar as it is purely monitory.
  • What desire there may be can never be for the vile; even the food and drink necessary for restoration will lie outside of the Soul's attention, and not less the sexual appetite;
  • or if such desire there must be, it will turn upon the actual needs of nature and be entirely under control; or if any uncontrolled motion takes place, it will reach no further than the imagination, be no more than a fleeting fancy.


Are you following all of this?

The follower of Plotinus is entirely unmoved by any of the ordinary affairs of human life. He eats and drinks only to calm his body. He is unmoved by fear, grief, or desire. He is either unaffected by pain or, if this is impossible, he refuses to allow it to have any power over him. He indulges his sexual desires only insofar as they pass fleetingly through his imagination. He is entirely free from "uncontrolled motion," but instead is a man entirely self-possessed:

The Soul itself will be inviolately free and will be working to set the irrational part of the nature above all attack, or if that may not be, then at least to preserve it from violent assault, so that any wound it takes may be slight and be healed at once by virtue of the Soul's presence, just as a man living next door to a Sage would profit by the neighbourhood, either in becoming wise and good himself or, for sheer shame, never venturing any act which the nobler mind would disapprove.
 

Nor is it correct, though, to see this as a constant battle between the Intellect and the passions. Instead,

There will be no battling in the Soul: the mere intervention of Reason is enough: the lower nature will stand in such awe of Reason that for any slightest movement it has made it will grieve, and censure its own weakness, in not having kept low and still in the presence of its lord.


 


 

 Welcome back to the Plotinus read-through! Today we'll continue to learn about virtue, and just how it is that (according to Plotinus) we're going to get out of this prison of matter. The prior post in this series is here. You can follow along with today's chapter here.

We come, so, to the question whether Purification is the whole of this human quality, virtue, or merely the forerunner upon which virtue follows? Does virtue imply the achieved state of purification or does the mere process suffice to it, Virtue being something of less perfection than the accomplished pureness which is almost the Term?

You really gotta love these translations.

Does virtue follow purification, or does virtue consist of purification? That's what the first sentence asks.

The second seems to reverse the order, suggesting that virtue is something of "less perfection" than "accomplished pureness."

I think the point is that, IF Virtue consists of the PROCESS of Purification, then the achieved state of Purity follows virtue.

On the other hand, purification might be a process which precedes the attainment of virtue.

Make sense? Let's read on.

To have been purified is to have cleansed away everything alien: but Goodness is something more.

If before the impurity entered there was Goodness, the Goodness suffices; but even so, not the act of cleansing but the cleansed thing that emerges will be The Good. And it remains to establish what this emergent is.

It can scarcely prove to be The Good: The Absolute Good cannot be thought to have taken up its abode with Evil. We can think of it only as something of the nature of good but paying a double allegiance and unable to rest in the Authentic Good.

 


We start with impurity. This, as we have seen, is the Soul's involvement with the Body, and with the passions that arise from material existence.

We must first cleans away this impurity. But, once we do so, are we left with Goodness? 

Not exactly, says Plotinus. Because The Good Itself cannot have become involved with evil-- that is, matter-- otherwise it would not be the Good! And yet, having been purified of evil, we have to be left with something LIKE the Good. Plotinus calls this "something of the nature of the good but paying a double allegiance" to both Good and Evil, Spirit and Matter.
 

The Soul's true Good is in devotion to the Intellectual-Principle, its kin; evil to the Soul lies in frequenting strangers. There is no other way for it than to purify itself and so enter into relation with its own; the new phase begins by a new orientation.

After the Purification, then, there is still this orientation to be made? No: by the purification the true alignment stands accomplished.

The Soul's virtue, then, is this alignment? No: it is what the alignment brings about within.

And this is...?

That it sees; that, like sight affected by the thing seen, the soul admits the imprint, graven upon it and working within it, of the vision it has come to.


The Soul's Good is devotion to the Intellectual-Principle.

Why is that?

The Soul is suspended between Intellect and Matter.

Intellect, remember, is not the thinking mind. Intellect is the realm of the Forms, those eternal powers which generate the world we experience. In Intellect, there is no discursive reasoning, because there is no separation. You don't have to think your way through a proof to understand something Intellectually. Instead, by Intellection, you immediately possess the object of knowledge-- becuase, in fact, there is no distinction between the subject and the object.

Does that make sense? If not, just let it be for now. Think of Intellect as the highest faculty of the soul, while the passions are the lowest. By purification we turn toward Intellect and away from Matter, toward the higher and eternal, rather than the lower and changeable, exactly as Plotinus told us to way back when.

When we turn toward Intellect, toward the highest part of our being, we are changed "like sight affected by the thing seen." Having seen it, we can't un-see it.

Plotinus asks the important question:
 

But was not the Soul possessed of all this always, or had it forgotten?

What it now sees, it certainly always possessed, but as lying away in the dark, not as acting within it: to dispel the darkness, and thus come to knowledge of its inner content, it must thrust towards the light.


In the Phaedrus, Plato suggests that we all once abided in the heavenly realms, with the Gods, but have since fallen, and forgotten. The process of spiritual awakening is, on this view, a process of REMEMBERING what we truly are. Plotinus seems to be building on this idea, suggesting that the vision of the Intellectual realm was always latent within us.

He concludes:
 

Besides, it possessed not the originals but images, pictures; and these it must bring into closer accord with the verities they represent. And, further, if the Intellectual-Principle is said to be a possession of the Soul, this is only in the sense that It is not alien and that the link becomes very close when the Soul's sight is turned towards It: otherwise, ever-present though It be, It remains foreign, just as our knowledge, if it does not determine action, is dead to us.


The Highest is always present and available to us. But it is up to us to turn towards it, and then to let it govern our actions. Otherwise, it means nothing.


 


 





Welcome back to the Plotinus read through!

One of the issues with taking any kind of break with this stuff is that of diving back in. The Platonic way of thinking is quite simply not the same as the modern. Learning to think as Plotinus and his predecessesors and successors do is challenging, and the tendency is to slip back into more familiar mental habits. I've found that I had to re-read my own earlier posts in this series in order to write this, and I kept saying, "Wow, that's a good point... I have no memory of writing it."

With that said, let's dive right back in. The preceding post in this series can be read here. You can follow along here.


We come now to that other mode of Likeness which, we read, is the fruit of the loftier virtues: discussing this we shall penetrate more deeply into the essence of the Civic Virtue and be able to define the nature of the higher kind whose existence we shall establish beyond doubt.

And so we are going to learn more about attaining Likeness with the divinity. There are, we are going to discover, two types of virtues, one of which is higher than the civic virtues of Courage, Justice, Prudence, and Temperance, we discussed previously.

Let's read on.

To Plato, unmistakably, there are two distinct orders of virtue, and the civic does not suffice for Likeness: "Likeness to God," he says, "is a flight from this world's ways and things": in dealing with the qualities of good citizenship he does not use the simple term Virtue but adds the distinguishing word civic: and elsewhere he declares all the virtues without exception to be purifications.

The civic virtues, it seems, are too bound up in the things of this world to lead to total Likeness.

But in what sense can we call the virtues purifications, and how does purification issue in Likeness?

A fine question.

As the Soul is evil by being interfused with the body, and by coming to share the body's states and to think the body's thoughts, so it would be good, it would be possessed of virtue, if it threw off the body's moods and devoted itself to its own Act- the state of Intellection and Wisdom- never allowed the passions of the body to affect it- the virtue of Sophrosyne- knew no fear at the parting from the body- the virtue of Fortitude- and if reason and the Intellectual-Principle ruled- in which state is Righteousness. Such a disposition in the Soul, become thus intellective and immune to passion, it would not be wrong to call Likeness to God; for the Divine, too, is pure and the Divine-Act is such that Likeness to it is Wisdom.

Okay, now we're getting into the meat of it.

As Plotinus told us at the beginning of this tractate, our first problem is that evil exists in this world, and therefore we must escape. Evil is rooted in matter, and not in soul, but our soul becomes evil by being intertwined with the body. Stuck here, we share the bodies urges and passions, and think the body's thoughts.

In order to become good and to attain virtue, the soul needs to rid itself of the thoughts and moods that are rooted in the body, and attend to its own proper acts.

And what is that proper act?

"Intellection and Wisdom."

Now, that word "Intellection" is an important one. It means the action of the Intellect. The word that is being rendered in English as "Intellect" is Nous, which is not translatable. The Intellectual, or Noetic, world is the world of Forms. The Forms, as we've seen already, are the eternal causal principles of the cosmos. Moreover, the Forms are always plural-- we can talk about this Form or that Form, but in practice, in the Intellectual Level, there is no separation. (And this is that much more true of the Gods, who have their existence at a level even higher than that of the Forms.) Intellection, thus, is a kind of automatic knowledge in which there is no distinction between the knower and the known.

As for "Wisdom," what he means by it depends upon what Greek word Plotinus is actually using. Often enough, that word is "dianoia," which means "through nous," and thus again refers to the Intellectual level of being.

He then adds that the soul free of the body's influence would possess the virtue of Sophrosyne or Temperance, in which it would be unmoved by the passions of the body. It would also possess Courage, by being unafraid to be parted from the body, and Justice ("Righteousness"), by being ruled by the highest part of itself-- the Nous.

This condition, Plotinus tells us, would make the Soul like unto God, because the divine is Intellective and immune to passion.

I may have missed something, but I'm not clear on where the second order of virtues we were promised comes in. Or is it simply that the virtues, when they condition a man to be a good citizen, are civic virtues, but when they condition his soul to Likeness with God, are something higher?

But would not this make virtue a state of the Divine also?

No: the Divine has no states; the state is in the Soul. The Act of Intellection in the Soul is not the same as in the Divine: of things in the Supreme, Soul grasps some after a mode of its own, some not at all.

One of the ideas we see in Platonic thinkers, that is found in later Christian theology also (though not its Protestant deviation), is that of Divine Simplicity. For Plotinus, there are no states, or changes in the condition, of God. "Divine wrath" is a metaphor whereby we humans can understand what naturally happens to us when we turn away from the Gods, but the Gods themselves don't literally get mad and huff about and fling thunderbolts. They don't have passions and do not need anything.

As for Intellection, I think it's right to say that Soul grasps the Intellectual World-- as it were-- from below, while the Gods grasp it from above. As we said before, the Gods don't need to be virtuous, because there is nothing for the virtues to save them from. They have nothing to fear, and so don't need courage, for example. But we could fear-- which is a bodily state, since it is our body that is harmed if what we are afraid of comes to pass. Courage allows us to become more like the Gods, who naturally know no fear, and thus to overcome the moods and thoughts of the body. Thus, there are two orders of virtue: Civic virtue, which makes us more useful citizens, and Virtue as purification.

This leads to a bit of a dilemma:

Then yet again, the one word Intellection covers two distinct Acts?

Rather there is primal Intellection and there is Intellection deriving from the Primal and of other scope.

And now Plotinus gives us one of the most interesting images we've had so far:

As speech is the echo of the thought in the Soul, so thought in the Soul is an echo from elsewhere: that is to say, as the uttered thought is an image of the soul-thought, so the soul-thought images a thought above itself and is the interpreter of the higher sphere.Virtue, in the same way, is a thing of the Soul: it does not belong to the Intellectual-Principle or to the Transcendence.

Speech is an echo of thought in the physical world. But thought itself, an action of the Soul, is also an echo of something higher. Intellection, as we said before, is automatic-- no separation between the knower and known, and thus no separation between, say, the parts of a sentence, or of a thought-act. Virtue is a thing of the Soul. It is thus an unfoldment of a simpler Something which is of the Intellectual World.

So: By the practice of the Virtues we purify ourselves, and shake off the power of the body. But the Virtues themselves aren't of the Intellectual world, or the Divine which is beyond it; instead they are like ladders, which unite our soul to its own highest principle, and that which is beyond.

 





Welcome back to our ongoing read-through of the Enneads of Plotinus!

Today we'll be looking at Ennead 1, Tractate 2, Section 2. As always, you can follow along online here. The first post in this series is here.

First, then, let us examine those qualities by which we hold Likeness comes, and seek to establish what is this thing which, as we possess it, in transcription, is virtue but as the Supreme possesses it, is the nature of an exemplar or archetype that is not virtue.

 
That sentence is a bit of a mouthful. Referring back to what we previously said, the virtues will lead us to the higher realm of the Gods, but those virtues are not useful there. God has nothing to be afraid of, and so doesn't need courage; he has no lower faculties to keep in line, and so has no need of temperance. But, in the Platonic world, Likeness never means "coincidental resemblance," as it does for us. If two things are Like one another, they share a quality which has a reality which might be higher than either of the two things in question. If the practice of a virtue will allow us to attain Likeness to God; but the virtue itself doesn't exist in the divine world; then the virtue that we experience must be a manifestation of a substance or process which is higher than the virtue as we know it.

Make sense? 

Well, let's keep reading anyway. 

We must first distinguish two modes of Likeness. 

There is the likeness of demanding an identical nature in the objects which, further, must draw their likeness from a common principle; and there is the case in which B resembles A, but A is a Primal, not concerned about B and not said to resemble B. In this second case, likeness is understood in a distinct sense: we no longer look for identity of nature, but, on the contrary, for divergence since the likeness has come about by the mode of difference.

Another way of saying this would be to talk about Horizontal and Vertical Likeness. A red book, a red candle, and a red coffee cup set beside one another are Like one another Horizontally. That is, they all share in common the color red, which is the same in each of them. On the other hand, their Likeness to Red Itself is Vertical. The cup has Red, but Redness Itself is unrelated to a cup. All of the cups in the world could be smashed to pieces or painted green, and red would be unaffected. Red is a Color, and it has that in common with Green, Blue, and Yellow. Color is a sensory quality, like texture, smell or weight. Sensory Quality could be compared with Non-Sensory Quality, such as Age or Durability. All of this is Plotinus's second mode of Likeness, which I'm calling Vertical Likeness. 

What, then, precisely is Virtue, collectively and in the particular? The clearer method will be to begin with the particular, for so the common element by which all the forms hold the general name will readily appear.

This is like starting with red and green to understand color, rather than starting with color in general.

The Civic Virtues, on which we have touched above, are a principle of order and beauty in us as long as we remain passing our life here: they ennoble us by setting bound and measure to our desires and to our entire sensibility, and dispelling false judgement-- and this by sheer efficacy of the better, by the very setting of the bounds, by the fact that the measured is lifted outside of the sphere of the unmeasured and lawless.

So: The civic virtues of justice, courage, temperance and wisdom set boundaries to our behavior. In doing so, they allow our behavior to be measured against a standard. Because of this, they lead to order. Order is a superior thing to chaos, and that which is bounded and measurable is superior to the unmeasurable. They limit the rule of our desires, which Plotinus has already described as being the lowest faculties of the soul, which ensnare us in matter.

It should probably be kept in mind here that the creation of the universe in the Platonic tradition is really a creation of order in the universe. The Demiurgos creates by taking the formless chaos and imposing structure upon it. By imposing structure on the chaos of our lives and our desires, we imitate the creator of the universe. 

And, further, these Civic Virtues-- measured and ordered themselves and acting as a principle of measure to the Soul which is as Matter to their forming-- are like to the measure reigning in the over-world, and they carry a trace of that Highest Good in the Supreme; for, while utter measurelessness is brute Matter and wholly outside of Likeness, any participation in Ideal-Form produces some corresponding degree of Likeness to the formless Being There. And participation goes by nearness: the Soul nearer than the body, therefore closer akin, participates more fully and shows a godlike presence, almost cheating us into the delusion that in the Soul we see God entire. 

This is the way in which men of the Civic Virtues attain Likeness.

This is what I said above. Notice, too, that the Virtues act on the Soul as God acted on Matter in the forming of the world. Analogy is also critically important in Platonic thinking. Here, God:Matter::Virtue:Soul. In an analogy, there is a likeness between the alternating terms; thus, by practicing Virtue, we produce a likeness of God within us. 

Again, and critically, the Analogy is not a mere coincidence or random resemblance of two disparate things. Not in Platonism. Here, Analogy is a timeless pattern of meaning and therefore one of the formative principles of the universe itself. Thus, Plotinus is being completely literal by saying that the Civic Virtues carry "a trace of that Highest Good in the Supreme." To be like something is to share a quality with something. By practicing the Civic Virtues we can become like God to such a degree that we can almost believe "that in the Soul we see God entire."
Welcome back!

When we last left Plotinus, he had established that the Soul does not, in fact, descend into the body, but remains in the world beyond. Instead it emits a kind of light which animates that body; the combination of light and body is called the Couplement. It is in the Couplement that we find many of our daily experiences, but not all of them. We ourselves are thus composite beings, and it is our task over the course of our lives to turn our attention away from this world, and toward the Higher.

But how shall we do that?

Let's see if we can find out!


Today we'll begin looking at the second tractate of the First Ennead. 

From here on out, our tractates become quite a bit longer. This is a good thing, because it will force me to do more summarizing, and less direct quoting. This may force me to think more, and even make this little blog a bit more readable. (Oh Steve, do you really think anybody's still reading this?) (Shut up, Brain. Back to typing!)

Anyway, Ennead 1, Tractate 2: On Virtue

Since Evil is here, "haunting this world by necessary law," and it is the Soul's design to escape from Evil, we must escape hence. 

But what is this escape?

"In attaining likeness to God," we read. And this is explained as "becoming just and holy, living by wisdom," the entire nature grounded in Virtue. 

 
From now on, all Plotinus's words are going to be indented, as above.

Now we're learning more about just what Plotinus's project is. As we learned previously, our Souls don't really descend into this material world. But they seem to, illuminating the material world from above. He doesn't tell us that this world is evil-- but Evil is here. And so to escape evil, we must escape the world?

But how?

Three things:

1. By becoming like God
2. Which means being just and holy, living by wisdom
3. Our entire nature grounded in virtue.

At this point, the Christian doctrine of Theosis comes forcefully to mind. This is the process-- little discussed in the West in recent centuries, but kept alive in the East, and recently coming back into prominence through the spread of Eastern Chrsitianity-- whereby human beings, through ascetic devotional practice, become participants in the divine nature. As St. Athanasius put it, "God became man, that men might become gods." You can read more here

Returning to Plotinus, though, what we're learning is that we need to get out of this world by becoming divine, and we do so by the practice of Virtue. What is Virtue, though? This is another word worse meaning has been corrupted in recent years, having come to mean something like "Girls shouldn't have sex" in the 19th century, and been abandoned entirely in the 20th century. But in Plotinus's day, Virtue had a more straightforward meaning. The virtues, plural, are particular excellences, the cultivation of which leads toward a particular good. In the Republic, Plato drew out 4 virtues as particularly important: Justice, Wisdom, Temperance and Courage. More on this in a moment.

Plotinus then discusses two different issue: To which divine being should we desire to attain likeness? And, does that being possess the virtues in question?

The answer to the first question:

To the Being-- must we not think? -- in Which, above all, such excellence seems to inhere, that is to the Soul of the Kosmos and to the Principle ruling within it, the Principle endowed with a wisdom most wonderful. What could be more fitting than that we, living in this world, should become like to its ruler?
 
But there's an issue, and it confused me at first. For Plotinus, how can the ruler of the universe possess courage, when he has nothing to fear, or temperance, when he isn't subject to temptation? But he answers the issue:

If, indeed, that aspiration towards the Intelligible which is in our nature exists also in this Ruling-Power, then we need not look elsewhere for the source of order and of the virtues in ourselves.
 
...

Huh.

Okay, let's try and understand this. The capitalized word "Intelligible" is important here. The "Intelligible" relates to the objects of Intellect. Intellect, in a Platonic context-- and, as always, this is my understanding, subject to refinement, change, and being altogether wrong-- does not mean what it does in common language. It is, instead, a translation of the Greek word nous. This is the highest part of our mind-- higher, actually, than our souls. It is the level of the Platonic Forms, which we've discussed before. The Intelligible is everything that we can grasp with Intellect. And-- this is important, and also very confusing at first-- at the level of Intellect, knowledge is automatic, because there is no distinction between the knower and the known. 

Now, going further, here is my understanding of Theology in Plato's world. The Demiurge-- that is, the creator God-- creates the world by first coming up with an idea of it. Think of the way that you'd create a painting; first you'd imagine it, then you'd put brush to paper. Well, the Idea of the World in the Mind of God is so big that it is, itself, a God. In that Idea are all the forms of which the material things on this world are only copies. I think we can call it Divine Mind, Intellect Itself, or Logos. That is the Divine Being to which Plotinus wants us to attain likeness, by means of the practice of Virtue. And since we have the aspiration toward that likeness, we know that it must come from the God himself-- what else could be its source?

But it's important for Plotinus to note that the God does not possess the virtues as we know them:

We cannot expect There to find what are called the Civic Virtues, the Prudence which belongs to the reasoning faculty; the Fortitude which conducts the emotional and passionate nature; the Sophrosyne which consists in a certain pact, in a concord between the passionate faculty and the reason; or the Rectitude which is the due application of the other virtues as each in turn should command or obey. 

 
Our Translator, in his usual delightful way, has given us Prudence, Fortitude, Sophrosyne, and Rectitude where we might otherwise have had Wisdom, Courage, Temperance and Justice. In either case, Plotinus makes an interesting point: Why would God need courage, when he has nothing to fear? Why would he need a concord between Passion and Reason, when he is above the passions that move us? And so on.

Plotinus offers the suggestion that, perhaps, we can't attain Likeness to God by these virtues, but by "those greater qualities known by the same general name". This suggests that there are higher versions of each of the virtues, which are applicable to the spiritual life, rather than to the civic life. He reconsiders, though, telling us that

It is against reason, utterly to deny Likeness by these while admitting it in the greater: tradition at least recognizes certain men of the civic excellence as divine, and we must believe that these too had attained some sort of likeness: on both levels there is virtue for us, though not the same virtue.

That is to say: The lesser manifestations of the virtues share in the power of the greater. It's worth remembering that for the Platonists, everything proceeds by Likeness. Nothing causes something altogether different from itself; there is always a middle term which unites the two. So if you have a lesser, civic-oriented Wisdom, it can't exist without a higher, spiritually-oriented Wisdom. The higher in some sense causes the lower, and therefore, is always present to the lower. Therefore, if the higher Wisdom leads to Likeness to the divine, the lower must also be able to affect this: "On both levels there is virtue for us, though not the same virtue." 


Plotinus next considers whether it is really possible for God to be without virtue-- as he's already shown must be the case. If a fire is warm-- he tells us-- must there be something else to warm the fire? Of course not. The fire is the source of warmth. God is the source of virtue. 

It is important for Plotinus that "virtue is one thing, the source of virtue another." He gives the following example, which helps to further illustrate what I think are some key aspects of Platonic thinking:

The material house is not identical with the house conceived in the intellect, and yet stands in its likeness: the material house has distribution and order while the pure idea is not constituted by any such elements; distribution order, symmetry are not parts of an idea.

So with us: it is from the Supreme that we derive order and distribution and harmony, which are virtues in this sphere: the Existences There, having no need of harmony, order or distribution, have nothing to do with virtue; and none the less, it is by our possession of virtue that we become like to Them.
 
All of this seems to me to be completely counter-intuitive from a Modern perspective. I think that there is a lot packed into these two little sentences-- most of it counterintuitive from a Modern perspective, all of it critical to understanding Plotinus's worldview. So let's wrap up by working through it.

Recall what I said above about the idea that precedes the object. The Demiurge conceives an Idea of the world; that Idea becomes the model of the world. A builder conceives an Idea for a house, and it becomes the model for the house. But there are qualities that the built house possesses-- virtues-- which are not in the idea of the house. These are the qualities of order, distribution and harmony-- the things that produce beauty here in the material world. The idea of the house doesn't need these things. And yet, the house, insofar as it has them, attains likeness to the idea, and manifests the idea here in the world. 

How can the civic virtues be similar to this? That's what we're asked-- I think-- to contemplate.

I think we're being given a Path of Ascent to the Divine, and I think it looks like this:

All of us have an Intellectual component to our being. That's the nous that I described above. It's above our Souls, or, to put it differently, it's the highest level of the Soul. 

That component is part of the Intelligible realm. That is to say, it's the eternal Idea of us that exists in the mind of the Creator. 

Remember that Ideas aren't passive objects. Ideas, which exist together on the Intelligible Plane, which can be understood both as a world unto itself, and as the Mind of God, and as itself a God, actively shape the world of our experience.

Now, suppose a builder, working on a house. In his mind he conceives of the best, most beautiful house he can imagine. In order to be beautiful in the material world, it will have to have the qualities of order, symmetry, harmony among its parts. 

But the house in the material world falls short of the Ideal house. It's disorderly; its parts don't fit together.

What if the house could change that? What if it could cultivate the qualities of order, harmony, symmetry?

In so doing, it would become more like the Idea of itself in the mind of its builder.

And remember what we said about about likeness. Likeness is not a chance resemblance among two separate things. Likeness is a type of causation, and things which are Like one another are present to one another.

By cultivating the virtues, we become Like ourselves as we exist in the Intelligible Realm. The Intelligible Realm is itself God and the Mind of God. Thus by cultivating the virtues, we attain Likeness and presence to God.

Is that what you're telling us, Plotinus?

Tune in next time, when maybe we'll find out!



Plotinus began-- if you can remember this long ago-- by asking about "pleasure and distress, fear and courage, desire and aversion-- where have these affections and experiences their seat?" 

Coming to the end of this tractate, we have the beginning of our answer.

The Soul, for Plotinus, is something that never enters into incarnation in the material world. The Soul exists, instead, in the world of Forms. Our individual Souls are forms, and they participate in the Universal Soul, which our translator sometimes renders Soul Itself. What is that? Well, if your body is a red object, your soul is the Color Red as it exists prior to any red objects. And Soul Itself is Color Itself, as it exists prior to any individual colors?

With me so far?

The experiences that we have in the world are the experiences of the Couplement of Soul and Body. Again, this Couplement doesn't exist by Soul descending into the material world. Instead, the Soul acts like a lantern, emitting a beam of light which illuminates the body as the lantern illuminates a wall. The Couplement is the illuminated wall.

All of our experiences in the material world are experiences of the illuminated wall. Our various material faculties are all powers of the soul refracted down through the couplement, "like images caught in a mirror," descending from sense-perception all the way down to the urge toward procreation.

We are thus hybrid beings, consisting of a Soul which is beyond the material world, and a set of faculties which allow us to act in the material world and which allow the material world to act upon us.

The consequences of this are as follows:

1. It is our choice where we direct our attention. In childhood, the lower faculties naturally dominate. Over the course of a lifetime, we gain the capacity to turn more and more toward the highest things-- if we choose. But we must choose.

2. On the other hand, our Soul Itself is blameless when it comes to our sinful acts. But we still must be purified of them. Plotinus mentions the possibility of descent into the Lower World after death, and of reincarnation as an animal.

****

3. This is not in Plotinus's work. It certainly seems to me, though, that considering the Soul as an ideal-form (like The Color Red) is another bit of evidence in favor of reincarnation. Consider-- we can discern the existence of the color red by the fact that there is a multitude of red objects. From this we can infer that there is something called "red," by which the red objects exist. If there was only-- not just one red object, but only one possible red object, anywhere in the entire universe, wouldn't it be harder to imagine a form of red? Wouldn't that object in fact BE the form of red-- since there is only one of it in existence or possible, and it cannot in any way be divided (because then there would be more than one of it)? Similarly, it seems that if our Souls are forms, then there must be more than one object animated by that form. These objects-- our bodies-- will then be separated in time rather than in space.

...And that's all for now. Join us next time, when we move on to the second tractate of the First Ennead!

Welcome back! Today, we look at the final section of the First Tractate of the First Ennead. As always, you can follow along here. The first post in this series is here.

Plotinus's words are in boldface; my comments in plain script. All that said, let's jump right in!

And the principle that reasons out these matters? Is it We or the Soul?

In other words, is it us down here below doing all this thinking, or is it the Soul itself?

We, but by the Soul.

How is that, then?

But how, "by the Soul"? Does this mean that the Soul reasons by possession [by contact with the matters of enquiry]?

Why not? I suppose: Insofar as those matters are things of the material world, the Soul cannot come into contact with them.

No; by the fact of being Soul. Its Act subsists without movement; or any movement that can be ascribed to it must be utterly distinct from all corporal movement and be simply the Soul's own life.

So.

We are illuminated by the Soul, as we have seen.

The Soul acts without movement, being beyond the material world. Reasoning, then, is something inherent in it. As we possess the Soul, so we possess reason. We do it, but without the Soul, we couldn't do it.

And Intellection in us is twofold: since the Soul is intellective, and Intellection is the highest phase of life, we have Intellection both by the characteristic Act of our Soul and by the Act of the Intellectual Principle upon us-- for this Intellectual-Principle is part of us no less than the Soul, and towards it we are ever rising.

...This is much easier to understand if you can visualize it.

As individuals, we have Souls, and we also have something higher than the Soul; we have the Intellect.

Do you remember way back in the day, when we said that a multitude of red objects all have the one thing in common-- the color red?

In the same way, a multitude of Souls all have in common Soul Itself. And a multitude of Intellects have in common Intellect Itself.

The intellectual Principle in an individual is to his personal Soul, as the Intellect Itself is to Soul Itself.

Thus, we have Intellect in two ways. First, we have our own Intellect, which acts upon our Soul directly. Second, we have Intellect Itself as it acts upon Soul Itself, and through Soul Itself, upon our individual Soul

...At least that's what I think Plotinus is saying. I'm basing this upon the fact that his much later intellectual descendant Proclus makes a big deal about this two-fold participation. (See Proclus, Elements of Theology, Propositions 108 and 109.)

It's worth noting, here, that Intellect in ancient Greek thought means something different than what it does for us. Intellect is the respository of the forms; in us, it is the highest aspect of the mind, which allows for contact with higher things and sudden leaps of insight.

(Anyway, that's how I understand it).

....And there you have it, folks!

We've made it through one tractate of one of Plotinus's Enneads!

Next, I'll post a summary of Tractate One, and we'll move on to Tractate Two. See you then!

Welcome back! Last time, we learned more about the Soul, and our relation to it. Today we'll look at Section 12 of Tractate 1 of the First of Plotinus's Enneads. As this is the second to the last section, that means we're almost done with this tractate! Can you believe it's only been... um... two and a half months? At this rate, we'll be done with the first Ennead... sometime in early 2022, if not sooner!

Dear Gods, I have to start doing this once a day, don't I?

Ugh.

Okay, we'll work our way up to that. For now, let's move on to Section 12. From now on, all Plotinus quotes are in bold, while my words are in plain text. The red I was using is hard on my eyes.

...

Now, we see, Plotinus comes to a dilemma:

But if the Soul is sinless, how come the expiations? Here surely is a contradiction; on the one side the Soul is above all guilt; on the other, we hear of its sin, its purification, its expiation; it is doomed to the lower world, it passes from life to life.

If the Soul is sinless, and we are the Soul, then why would we need to spend time in the lower worlds, or reincarnated in lower conditions, to work off our guilt after we die? 

We may take either view at will; they are easily reconciled.

But how, Plotinus?

When we tell of the sinless Soul, we make Soul and Essential-Soul one and the same; it is the simple and unbroken Unity.

Ah. That is how. The eternal and unchanging part of us remains always sinless. It is only when we enter into material incarnation that we can do evil. Just as we learned that the eternal Soul doesn't suffer pain when our body hurts, or lust, or rage, or whathaveyou, so presumably it doesn't suffer the pain of being reborn in the Lower World, or in the body of an animal, if that is our fate after death.

...Is that right?

By the Soul subject to sin we indicate a groupment, we include that other, that phase of the Soul which knows all the states and passions; the Soul in this sense is compound, all-inclusive; it falls under the conditions of the entire living experience: this compound it is that sins; it is this, and not the other, that pays the penalty.

...Yes, that is right.

It is in this sense that we read of the Soul: "We saw it as those others saw the sea-god Glaukos." "And," reading on, "if we mean to discern the nature of the Soul we must strip it free of all that has gathered about it, must see into the philosophy of it, examine with what Existences it has touch and by kinship to what Existences it is what it is."

I'm told that "we read" always means Plato. And I'm not sure where in Plato these passages are to be found. So let us read on, and see where this is going.

Thus Life is one thing, the Act is another, and the Expiator yet another. The retreat and sundering, then, must not be from this body only, but from every alien accruement. Such accruement takes place at birth; or rather birth is the coming-into-being of that other [lower] phase of the Soul. For the meaning of birth has been indicated elsewhere; it is brought about by a descent of the Soul, something being given off by the Soul other than that actually coming down in the declension.

This is to say: In the act of death, the lower doesn't only separate itself from the body. It separates, also, from everything which came into being during its time on Earth-- everything that Plotinus has previously described as the lower phases of the Soul, from sensory perception of material objects all the way on down to the impulse to procreate.

Here is a question-- Do the "expiations" after death consist of purifying the soul of everything that accrued to it during life? Is that what is meant by "reward and punishment"?

In the myth of Er in the Republic, Plato describes a place of judgment where we all find ourselves after death. In this place there are two holes in the ground, and two holes in the heavens. One of the holes into ground leads into the Underworld; the other leads back out again. The same with the holes in the heavens-- one leads to Heaven, the other back out. After death, those who have sinned get to take the first hole down into Hell, to undergo punishment. Once they've had enough, they come back up the second hole. At that point they can go back into incarnation. Conversely, the just get to go up to Heaven for a while, via the entrance hole; once they've been sufficiently rewarded, they get to come back down and head back for another earthly life. All except those who have been good enough to merit remaining in the Upper World permanently... and those whose guilt is so great they are stuck in the lower world for good.

For Plotinus, is the upper world the return of the Soul to its proper place among the divine? And is the lower world the expiation of everything nasty and material that is has accumulated during its sojourn on Earth?

Then the Soul has let this image fall? And this declension is not certainly sin?

...That is, isn't it sinful to come down here in the first place?

If the declension is no more than the illuminating of an object beneath, it constitutes no sin: the shadow is to be attributed not to the luminary but to the object illuminated; if the object were not there, the light could cause no shadow.

...Because the Soul isn't really involved in the actions of the Couplement; it only makes those actions possible. We sin, meanwhile, when we direct our attention downward, toward the material world, the body and its urges, without allowing our higher faculties to become involved, as we have seen previously. The question remains, though-- Why has the Soul entered into incarnation at all?

The following is very interesting:

And the Soul is said to go down, to decline, only in that the object it illuminates lives by its life. And it lets the image fall only if there be nothing near to take it up; and it lets it fall, not as a thing cut off, but as a thing that cases to be; the image has no further being when the whole Soul is looking toward the Supreme.

...And it's another instance where a better translation, some notes, or-- perhaps best of all-- the ability on my part to read ancient Greek. What is meant by the phrase "let the image fall"?

For us here below, life consists of being "illuminated," as it were, by something higher than us-- our Soul. We live insofar as the Soul shines its light upon the mass of our bodies. From this, we gain our faculties of perceiving and acting upon the material world.

If there is "nothing near to take up the image" the Soul "lets it fall" as "a thing that ceases to be." The image, then, is the lower soul. When we die, the lower soul ceases to be, and we withdraw to the higher.

But I think there is more to it than that-- spiritual practice in this life consists of turning toward the higher, the whole Soul toward the Supreme.

He illustrates this with an example from legend:

The poet, too, in the story of Hercules, seems to give this image separate existence; he puts the shadow of Hercules in the lower world and Hercules himself among the gods: treating the hero as existing in the two realms at once, he gives us a twofold Hercules.

It is not difficult to explain this distinction. Hercules was a hero of practical virtue. By this noble servicableness he was worthy to be a God. On the other hand, his merit was action and not the Contemplation which would place him unreservedly in the higher realm. Therefore while he has place above, something of him remains below

We learned earlier that those virtues which arise from bodily discipline are things of the Couplement, while those arising only from the Soul are higher virtues. Insofar as Hercules won renown by thrashing about the land killing monsters and the like, he remains a hero of "practical virtue," because his merit is "action" and not "the Contemplation which would place him unreservedly in the higher realm."

It is Contemplation-- note the capital-- which earns us a place in the higher realm, not action or practical virtue.




 Welcome back! Last time we worked through the 10th section of the first tractate of the first of Plotinus's Enneads. Today we'll move on to Section 11

Let's jump right back in.

In childhood the main activity is in the Couplement and there is but little irradiation from the higher principles of our being: but when these higher principles act but feebly or rarely upon us their action is directed towards the Supreme; they work upon us only when they stand at the mid-point.

Last time, we saw that, for Plotinus, the Soul is not identical with the experiencing self. The Soul is an eternal principle, beyond material incarnation. The total person-- the human system, if you like-- is like a series of beads on a string. The highest bead is the Soul. The lowest represents the faculties of generation. Our experience is able to range up and down the string, connected to this bead or that bead according to circumstances.

Here, Plotinus is telling us that, in the early part of our life, most of our experience is centered here below, in the life of the body. I think that this is something anyone would agree with, and it certainly fits my own experience of childhood through roughly age 30.

The last section appears to be another victim of this garbled and half-comprehensible translation. We are told that "when these higher principles act but feebly or rarely upon us their action is directed towards the Supreme" and also that "they work upon us only when they stand at the mid-point." 

But does not the We include that phase of our being which stands above the mid-point?

(The word "We" in this sentence is missing in the link I provided.)

Okay, this clarifies the previous sentence a bit. It appears that he means that the higher principles of our being are acting above the mid-point. When we ourselves are experiencing life below that mid-point-- the mean between Soul and Body-- we are unaware of them. And here he responds to the objection, but isn't that higher part of us, well, part of us? 

It does, but on the condition that we lay hold of it: our entire nature is not ours at all times but only as we direct the mid-point upwards or downwards, or lead some particular phase of our nature from potentiality or native character into act.

Are you following this? This is, it seems to me, a critical idea. Parts of us only exist in potential, and parts of us are beyond manifestation in the material world. They are, indeed, part of us. But our talents are only real insofar as we manifest them as skills. And our higher spirit is only a part of us insofar as we turn our attention towards it, and unite ourselves to it, through spiritual practice, rather than to our lower self, through obeying our bodily urges, passions and impulses. 

This next part is neat:

And the animals, in what way or degree do they possess the Animate?

If there be in them, as the opinion goes, human Souls that have sinned, then the Animating-Principle in its separable phase does not enter directly into the brute; it is there but not there to them; they are aware only of the image of the Soul [only of the lower Soul] and of that only by being aware of the body organised and determined by that image.

If there be no human Soul in them, the Animate is constituted for them by a radiation from the All-Soul.


In the Timaeus, Plato has it that we are first born into the bodies of men. If we mess up, we're reborn as women. If we mess up a second time, we are reborn as animals. 

This idea is clearly reflective of the prejudices of its age, and is unacceptable to the modern reader. (In the same way, many of our prejudices will not be revealed as such for 1, 2, 5 or 10 centuries; then they will appear cruel and nonsensical in just the same way.) However, it is interesting to note that, for Plotinus, only those animals who were previously human beings have individualized souls-- with which they are unable to make contact in this life. For the rest, their soul is actually a group soul-- the Universal Soul. 

To my mind, it makes more sense to view animals as possessing individual souls as do we, though they are far more removed from them than we are. Some animals would indeed be human beings that have failed to make it at the human level, and were sent back a grade, so to speak. Others would be our younger brothers and sisters, on the journey with us.

It's also fun to consider that at least some animals are at the same level we are. This may be incorrect, but I like to think that dolphins and whales, and also parrots or crows, are at the same level as human beings. This allows for there to People of the Earth, Sea and Sky. 

Now, it's also worth taking a minute to view the world the way Plotinus would have, on his own terms. What would it mean to think of animals as participants in the Universal Soul? What would it mean to think of ourselves the way that he does?
And so do we resume our long, slow, slog through the Enneads of Plotinus, with the 10th section of the first tractate of the first Ennead. The last entry can be read here. If you'd like to follow along, you can do so here.

Last time, we saw that the soul does not share the blame for our sins, because it stands apart from the Couplement of Soul and body. When we fall into lust, wrath, and similar states, it is because we have turned our attention only to the body, without involving or invoking our Soul and our higher faculties. Sinful behavior, then, is like an illusion which fools the eyes before the rational mind can overcome it.

It will be objected-- says Plotinus, in the opening to Section 10-- that if the Soul constitutes the We [the personality] and We are subject to these states then the Soul must be subject to them, and similarly that what We do must be done by the Soul.

This was my objection on first reading this. My initial assumption was that the Soul is what, in Hindu philosophy, is called the "observer"-- the True Self that experiences bodily and mental states, and is otherwise simple, and contentless. In Hindu thought, it is this that persists from one life to the next. That view has always made sense to me, and I had assumed Plotinus was using "Soul" in the same sense. That leads to a bit of confusion, though, because he clearly is not. For Plotinus, the total person is something more like a series of beads on a string, with the highest representing the soul, the lowest the body, and the rest the faculties that lie in between.

In this way of looking at things, the observing faculty is able to range up and down the length of the system, from the lowest reaches of the Couplement-- that's where those nasty generative faculties are found-- up to the Soul itself. Indeed, the task of the philosopher, for Plotinus, seems to be to withdraw from the Couplement to the greatest extent possible.

He goes on:

But it has been observed that the Couplement, too- especially before our emancipation- is a member of this total We, and in fact what the body experiences we say We experience. This then covers two distinct notions; sometimes it includes the brute-part, sometimes it transcends the brute. The body is brute touched to life; the true man is the other, going pure of the body, natively endowed with the virtues which belong to the Intellectual-Activity, virtues whose seat is the Separate Soul, the Soul which even in its dwelling here may be kept apart. [This Soul constitutes the human being] for when it has wholly withdrawn, that other Soul which is a radiation [or emanation] from it withdraws also, drawn after it.

Notice that line, "before our emancipation." In the Phaedo, Plato has Socrates compare the work of the philosopher to death. The philosopher is the lover of wisdom, and he does his best work when he is not attending to the body's needs, nor encumbered by its deficiencies.

In death, we are freed from the need to eat and drink, from the urges toward sex or wealth or anger. Is Plotinus using the term "our emancipation" specifically to refer to death, or to refer also to the work of transcending the body and uniting with the higher soul in this life?.

In either case, according to Plotinus's reasoning, the Soul remains blameless of our bad behaviors and disordered states, in the same way that the lantern that shines its light on the wall is uninvolved with the events of the wall itself. And when the lantern's shutter is closed, the light withdraws, and the wall is as it was before.

This is interesting:

Those virtues, on the other hand, which spring not from contemplative wisdom but from custom or practical discipline belong to the Couplement: to the Couplement, too, belong the vices; they are its repugnances, desires, sympathies.

The Virtues, for the ancient and medieval world, are particular excellences which human beings can achieve. Plotinus here suggests that those virtues which arise from discipline belong to the Couplement.

Now, the case could certainly be made that the ability to sit down every morning and enter into meditation is a practical discipline, and yet it is this practical discipline that allows us to attain the kinds of higher faculties that belong to the Soul. This suggests that, even on a Plotinian account of the world and the human being, we reach the highest things by starting with lower things.

He leaves us with the following:

And Friendship?

This emotion belongs sometimes to the lower part, sometimes to the interior man.

It is interesting to reflect on this. Which friendships belong to the lower part, which to the interior man? I suppose the answer must be, it depends upon the motive behind the friendship. Is it the sort of friendship that leads to the cultivation of the life of the Soul, or is it the sort of friendship that arises from our lower nature? 

Well, which friendships arise from our lower nature? I suppose-- those which are similar to the sorts of friendships animals make, which amount to displays of play or submission to higher-ranking members of their group, or to their parents. How many of our friendships amount to the same thing? 

Consider the typical American high school. How many "friendships" are based on either general "popularity" or membership in a particular "clique"? 

And, having been entrained by so many years of that, and not being trained at all in the cultivation of the life of the mind, how many of us continue these patterns all throughout our lives?

 







 ...In an irritating turn of events, Dreamwidth decided to delete this post, which was halfway completed. But let's not let that get us down, let's jump right back into the Enneads! As always, you can follow along here; the last post in this series can be read here.

Last time, Plotinus elaborated on his view of the Soul as existing apart from the body, and uniting with the body only be emitting a kind of light (this is a metaphor) which animates the body, like a wall illuminated by the lantern. 

That Soul, then, in us, will in its nature stand apart from all that can cause any of the evils which man does or suffers; for all such evil, as we have seen, belongs only to the Animate, the Couplement.

Have you got that? The Soul is not affected by the actions of the Couplement-- that is, the animated body-- anymore than the lantern is affected by what happens on the wall. 

But there is a difficulty in understanding how the Soul can go guiltless if our mentation and reasoning are vested in it: for all this lower kind of knowledge is delusion and is the cause of much of what is evil.

That is-- if the Soul is responsible for thinking, and most of our thinking is evil, how can it be blameless of evil?

When we have done evil it is because we have been worsted by our baser side-- for a man is many-- by desire or rage or some evil image: the false, in reality fancy, has not stayed for the judgement of the Reasoning-Principle: we have acted at the call of the less worthy, just as in matters of the sense-sphere we sometimes see falsely because we credit only the lower perception, that of the Couplement, without applying the tests of the Reasoning-Faculty.

The image that keeps coming to mind is of the human person as a kind of center of gravity, suspended between two poles. At the one extreme is our Higher Soul, united with the Divine Mind; at the other is the lower passions, moving us toward rage or lust. We have a choice in any given instance as to which direction to go. Which of course returns us to the question of which part of us really is the "us." And it suggests that the answer is: We have a choice. We can remember our higher nature, that is, the lantern, removed from the wall; or we can take the things on the wall-- spiders or dust or whatever-- as our reality, and go toward them.

The Intellectual-Principle has held aloof from the act and so is guiltless; or, as we may state it, all depends on whether we ourselves have or have not put ourselves in touch with the Intellectual-Realm either in the Intellectual-principle or within oruselves; for it is possible at once to possess it and not to use it.

"For a man is many." I wonder, though-- if a part of us is innocent, another part guilty, and yet we can choose between the two, is not that part of us that makes the choice-- the will, call it-- the true man? Would that not then be prior either to Soul or to Couplement or to Body?

Thus we have marked off what belongs to the Couplement from what stands by itself: the one group has the character of body and never exists apart from body, while all that has no need of body for its manifestation belongs peculiarly to Soul: and the Understanding, as passing judgement upon Sense-Impressions, is at the point of the vision of Ideal-Forms, seeing them as it were with an answering sensation (i.e., with consciousness) this last is at any rate true of the Understanding in the Veritable Soul. For Understanding, the true, is the Act of the Intellections: in many of its manifestations it is the assimilation and reconciliation of the outer to the inner.

I really, really like how our translator just kinds of tosses out brand new Capitalized Terms that we've never seen before, without any explanatory notes, as though the mere fact of Using Capital Letters was enough to point them out as Important and in that way to Explain Their Meaning.

I also love how grammatical the English here is. 

Well, anyway, let's give this one a go. This one giant sentence of a paragraph is ridiculously long, so let's take it clause by clause.

Thus we have marked off what belongs to the Couplement from what stands by itself: the one group has the character of body and never exists apart from body

Everything that we experience that belongs to the Couplement is characterized by being bodily, and not existing apart from the body. We experience hunger, it's a real thing, but we can't experience it without our body. On the other hand...

all that has no need of body for its manifestation belongs peculiarly to Soul

Simple enough...

and the Understanding, as passing judgement upon Sense-Impressions, is at the point of the vision of the Ideal-Forms

Have we met a capital-U Understanding before? I can't remember. Either way, whatever it is, its job is to pass judgment upon sense impressions. Because of this it is at the point of the vision of the Ideal-Forms. How is that? It must be-- I see an object with my eyes. My Understanding says "A red balloon." Both "red" and "balloon" exists as ideal forms, apart from this specific red thing, this specific balloon. Therefore, the Understanding is at the point of contact with the Forms-- looking up at them from below, as it were. Or, to say it another way,

seeing them with an answering sensation

Right.

this last is true, at any rate, of the Understanding in the Veritable Soul.

So it is our true, or our higher, Soul that has the faculty of the Understanding.

For Understanding, the true, is the Act of the Intellections: in many of its manifestations it is the assimilation and reconciliation of the outer to the inner.

We have nothing to explain or contextualize this statement, and thus nothing but guesswork to go on when trying to understand it. Still, it's a fascinating thing to say. Understanding-- What did we just learn that is? The faculty of judgement in the Soul. It works with the Intellections-- that connects us both to the eternal Forms and the idea of Divine Mind. And he tells us that it is often "the assimilation and reconciliation of the outer to the inner." In other words...

What?

I see an object. 

My Understanding judge: It's a red balloon. I have experience of red, and of balloons. Is that what this is? Yes, it is. Or, no-- I'm wrong, it's a red plane, or an orange balloon, or a cloud. Now I revise my judgment. Is this how it works? 

I suspect so. Because, remember what he said earlier about the Soul going blameless in our misdeeds? And he used the image of a sense object misunderstood. We see something and react immediately-- Say, we are hiking in the woods, see a snake, and immediately jump. But then we apply our Understanding-- it's not a snake at all, it's just a stick! The Understanding, seated in the Soul, was absent from our original action, and thus we made a mistake. 

If that's so, we can conclude this section with Plotinus:

Thus in spite of all, the Soul is at peace as to itself and within itself: all the changes and all the turmoil we experience are the issue of what is subjoined to the Soul, and are, as we have said, the states and experiences of this elusive Couplement.


Welcome back!

Last time, Plotinus began to wrap up his view on the nature of the Soul and its relation to the body, telling us that the Soul acts like a kind of light, shining into the body, like a lantern lighting up a wall. What is he going to tell us this time? Let's dive in and find out!

As always, if you want to follow along, you can do so here.

And towards the Intellectual-Principle what is our relation? By this I mean, not that faculty in the soul which is one of the emanations from the Intellectual-Principle, but The Intellectual-Principle itself [Divine Mind].

As I understand it, Intellect in Platonic philosophy is the realm of the Forms, those eternal Things that allow changeable things here in the world to have qualities. The example I keep using, of course, is red, which is a form under the larger heading Color, in which it participates along with green, blue, and so on; and which itself is under the still larger heading Quality, along with shape, texture, etc.

Here, Plotinus isn't talking about our capacity to perceive forms, which is something we receive, but the "The Intellectual Principle itself." In other words, Intellect as it exists before individuals have intelects. Or, to say it another way, the Mind of God.

This we also possess as the summit of our being. And we have it either as common to all or as our own immediate possession: or again we may possess It in both degrees, that is in common, since It is indivisible--one, everywhere and always Its entire self-- and severally in that each personality possesses It entire in the First-Soul [i.e. in the Intellectual as distinct from the lower phase of the Soul.]

The Intellectual Principle is a unity; it can't be divided. And yet each of us, in the highest part of our individual soul, experiences it individually.

Hence we possess the Ideal-Forms also after two modes: in the Soul, as it were unrolled and separate; in the Intellectual-Princi[ple, concentrated, one.

And so we can say the same thing about the Forms. At their highest, they can't be divided, and so we each possess them just as they are-- and yet we do so individually, "unrolled and separate" in our individual consciousness. 




And how do we possess the Divinity?

Here we have to add a caveat. What does our translator mean by "the Divinity?" In the absence of notes, we don't know. In the Platonic tradition we have an idea of the Highest God, who precedes the individual Gods. Is that what Plotinus means, or is he talking about how we commune with specific deities, or is he talking about how we are able to interact with divinity (God, Gods) in general? 

(Note to self: Find time to learn ancient Greek.)

Let's see what he says, and see if we can make sense of it.

In that the Divinity is contained in the Intellectual-Principle and Authentic-Existence; and We come third in order after these two, for the We is constituted by a union of the supreme, the undivided Soul-- we read-- and that Soul which is divided among [living] bodies. For, note, we inevitably think of  the Soul, though one and undivided in teh All, as being present to bodies in division: in so far as any bodies are Animates, the Soul has given itself to each of the separate material masses; or rather it appears to be present in the bodies by the fact that it shines into them: it makes them living beings not by merging into body but by giving forth, without any change in itself, images or likenesses of itself like one fact caught by many mirrors.

Let's work through this backwards. Plotinus concludes this bit with my favorite image so far. The Soul is present to the body like one image reflected through a series of mirrors. Each of these images, we'll soon discover, gets further and further from the eternal principle of Soul-- but let's set that aside for now. We are constituted by a union of the eternal Soul and that Soul which is divided among bodies. The Divinity, meanwhile, is contained in "the Intellectual-Principle and Authentic-Existence." This is the second time we've encountered this term "Authentic-Existence"; our delightful translator just throws it in there, capital letters and hyphenations, assuming we'll know what he means. Fortunately, we know that our order of existence goes: The One, The Intellect, Soul. "Divinity" is contained in "the Intellectual-Principle" and "Authentic-Existence"; the latter therefore means either the One itself, or else is a term for the life of the Soul as an eternal Form. It doesn't really matter which: In either case, Plotinus is saying that since we participate in Intellect and Soul, it is in this way that we have access to the Divine.

Now he's going to have something very interesting to say about all those images, caught in those mirrors:

The first of these images is Sense-Perception seated in the Couplement; and from this downwards all the successive images are to be recognized as phases of the Soul in lessening succession from one another, until the series ends in the faculties of generation and growth and of all production of offspring-- offspring efficient in its turn, in contradistinction to the engendering Soul which [has no direct action within matter but] produces by mere inclination towards what it fashions.

Reading this, were you reminded of the Tree of Life? This is the diagram made famous by Jewish Cabalists, but which probably originates with Gnostics contemporary with Plotinus himself. The Tree is a model both of the universe and the individual. In it, life begins in an absolute Monad (Kether) and proceeds through 9 permutations, making its way through Mind, Emotion, Sense-Perception, and finally the urge toward reproduction (Yesod), and then gives rise to material reality (Malkuth). 

It's worth noting that, in the Cabala, matter is only the last, most tenuous expression of spirit; for Plotinus, on the other hand, the Soul "has no direct action within matter."



Have you heard of the Watcher at the Threshold? That's the thing that turns up every time you start a new project-- running or meditating every day, finally writing that book, drinking less coffee, whatever it is. At some point, you make it one day, the next, the third day, and then, there he is. He's the thing that says, "Maybe I just won't do it today. I'll get to it tomorrow." And then tomorrow comes and you're like, "But I already didn't do it yesterday, so why today?" Eventually it's a week later, and you say to yourself, "I guess I don't do it after all," and so you stop.

This is a new project for me, so it's not surprising that the Watcher turned up. Of course, he was greatly assisted by the unbelievable level of busy-ness of my life lately. But these little posts don't take that long, and so, with all due respect to Mr. Watcher, let's jump right back in.



 In this section, Plotinus begins to wind up his argument about the soul. He starts by telling us what's really going on here:

The truth lies in the Consideration that the Couplement subsists by virtue of the Soul's presence.

This, however, is not to say that the Soul gives itself as it is in itself to form either the Couplement or the body.

No; from the organized body and something else, let us say a light, which the Soul gives forth by itself, it forms a distinct Principle, the Animate; and in this principle are vested Sense-Perception and all other experiences found to belong to the Animate.

Are you following, so far? In Plotinus's view, the Soul remains beyond physical incarnation, in the way (I think) that redness remains beyond a specific red object. So the Soul isn't present to the body the way that it is all by itself-- instead it's like something comes forth from it. He uses the metaphor of a light-- in this case, it would be as if a wall were illuminated by a lantern. The illuminated wall is the "Couplement" of wall and light. The lantern remains a separate thing, in a separate place, but the light on the wall is only possible through it. 

Are you reminded of those modern thinkers who describe consciousness as akin to a radio signal that is received by the brain?

More:

But the "We"? How have We Sense Perception?

By the fact that We are not separate from the Animate so constituted, even though certanily other and nobler elements go to make up the entire many-sided nature of Man.

In the same way that the lantern is not separate from the wall it illuminates, we are not separate from the body, or, rather, the complex of body and Soul. But:

The faculty of perception in the Soul cannot act by the immediate grasping of sensible objects, but only by the discerning of impressions printed upon the Animate by sensation: these impressions are already Intelligibles while the outer sensation is a mere phantom of the other [of that in the Soul] which is nearer to Authentic-Existence as being an impassive reading of Ideal-Forms.

....And this is one of those moments where I wish either that I read ancient Greek, or else that the editor of this volume had bothered to include notes to explain his choice of English words, including Capitalizations. In the absence of these, much of this is gobbledy-gook. That said, let's unpack what we can.

Since the Soul is beyond embodiment, it can't grasp the objects of perception directly. Light enters the eye, and you see an image of a computer screen. In the material world, that's all that is happening; the image produced is something else, and is not material. For Plotinus, the image that is created in the mind (as we would say) is more real than the light entering the brain. After all, in the mind the image becomes an image of a computer screen, or the color red-- and this is touches on the world of permanent forms. 

And by means of these Ideal-Forms, by which the Soul wields single lordship of the Animate, we have Discursive-Reasoning, Sense-Knowledge and Intellection. From this moment we have peculiarly the We: before this there was only the "ours"; but at this stage stands to WE (the authentic human-principle] loftily presiding over the Animate.

I've got to tell you, I am not at all sure why this should be so.

Let's accept it as a premise for now. It's worth keeping in mind that Plotinus was writing in an era that was utterly sick of living in the material world. He was only slightly less extreme than the Gnostics, and only because he didn't believe that the Creator God was actually an evil demon. For now, we have the idea that the Soul, because it is outside of embodiment and capable of reason, and of perceiving Ideal-Forms (in part by means of sense-objects), presides loftily over the body.

There is no reason why the entire compound entity should not be described as the Animate or Living-Being-- mingled in a lower phase, but above that point the beginning of the veritable man, distinct from all that is kin to the lion, all that is of the order of the multiple brute. And since The Man, so understood, is essentially the associate of the reasoning Soul, in our reasoning it is this "we" that reasons, in that the use and act of reason is a characteristic act of the Soul.

At its highest, the Soul of man is above embodiment, and above both sense perceptions and the urges of nature that govern "the multiple brute." Indeed, it is the task of philosophy to raise human beings to the level of true human beings, not mere beasts in clothes. As our later author from the same tradition writes, "He alone is perfect who attains the highest level of knowledge, and delights in and loves that level of knowledge. They were called 'philosophers' in Greek, and in Latin this word is properly interpreted 'lovers of knowledge.' Whoever does not strive for knowledge is defective and weak in authority, and therefore ought not to be called human, despire having the name, form, and figure of a human being."*



*Picatrix Bk 1 Ch 6, Greer and Warnock trans.
Welcome back!

You may notice from the slightly different title that I'm messing with the format of this blog a bit.

It occurred to me that it might be slightly tedious for some to follow along with the line-by-line expositions I've been doing. My plan is to write a post summarizing the basic arguments and conclusion of each tractate once I reach the end of it; to read those posts, you won't have to read along with Mr. Plotinus himself. It may be a little while between those, though. In the meantime, you're welcome to follow along as I struggle to make sense of this!

Last time, Plotinus determined that experience could not be rooted in the Couplement of Soul and Body. Certain affections, he pointed out, giving sexual arousal as an example, require the body, while others are based in the Soul alone. Meanwhile, it isn't clear whether the affections originate in the body or the Soul. How can this be? Let's continue to read and see what we find out! As always, you can follow along here

It may seem reasonable to lay down as a law that when any powers are contained by a recipient, every action or state expressive of them must be the action or state of that recipient, they themselves remaining unaffected as merely furnishing efficiency.

To say this another way: consider motion. A thing in motion moves-- it is the recipient of the power of motion. But Motion itself remains unaffected.

But if this were so, then, since the Animate is the recipient of the Causing-Principle [i.e., the Soul] which brings life to the Couplement, this Cause must itself remain unaffected, all the experiences and expressive activities of the life being vested in the recipient, the Animate.

If I understand correctly, then if the relationship of Soul to body is like motion to a moving thing, then the Soul would not have any experiences at all-- because it cannot be affected, if this is the case. If that were the case, what would the Soul even be? Plotinus anticipates this problem, saying--

But this would mean that life itself belongs not to the Soul but to the Couplement; or at least the life of the Couplement would not be the life of the Soul; Sense-Perception would belong not to the Sensitive-Faculty but to the container of the faculty. 




If this is the case, then your Soul is basically detached from your body, experiencing nothing, not even life; it's just there as a kind of outside cause, enabling life to happen. But this doesn't make sense--

But if sensation is a movement traversing the body and culminating in Soul, how can the soul lack sensation? The very presence of the Sensitive-Faculty must assure sensation to the Soul. 

Once again, where is sense-perception seated?

In the Couplement.

Yet how can the Couplement have sensation independently of action in the Sensitive-Faculty, the Soul left out of count and the Soul-Faculty?


Plotinus is about to bring this section to conclusion, in the chapter to follow. 

As stated above, my plan is to continue to go through these one chapter at a time-- there are 13 total chapters, so we're almost at the halfway mark. At that point, I will summarize the basic argument and the conclusions, and give some thoughts on it. And then we'll move forward!

Now, if you're following along and finding Plotinus makes your head hurt, don't despair. I plan to alternate close reads of The Enneads with more broadly-focused posts on complete works, like the one I did on Dion Fortune below. Specific texts I want to consider include Hesiod's Theogony, a medieval Taoist meditation manual entitled The Secret of the Golden Flower, and Catholic St. Louis de Montfort's book of Mariology, True Devotion to the Blessed Virgin Mary. What do all of these have in common with each other? Stick around, and maybe we'll find out!
Welcome back to my attempt to make sense of that most difficult works of classical philosophy, the Enneads of Plotinus, with no formal training nor facility in the original language!

Today we're going to be looking at the 5th chapter, of the first tractate, of the first Ennead. As always you can follow along here. 

I wrote about 80% of this blog post yesterday, then foolishly left my computer unattended overnight. In the meantime it appears to have restarted itself and, in the process, deleted everything I wrote. So this post might be abbreviated-- which might be for the beter.

Last time, Plotinus concluded that the Soul does not experience affectations-- particularly, it seems, negative ones such as suffering-- but that these are, rather, experienced by something called "the Animate." Again, I am assuming that "Animate" is our translator's way of rendering a Greek word meaning "ensouled being" or "living being." I am also assuming, or provisionally concluding, that Plotinus's reasoning is similar to the following:

Red is a concept or quality shared by red objects in general, such as a red book, a red candle, or a red bulb on a Christmas tree. 
The Soul is similar to red, as a non-physical form.
Just as the color red as a whole is unaffected by the burning out of a red candle or by a red book being covered by a green dust jacket, so the soul is not affected by the experiences of the body.
Those experiences, instead, are had by something called "the Animate," which is the body-that-has-a-soul, in the same way that the candle is a candle-that-has-redness.

Plotinus has given other examples of non-corporeal forms which are united with matter to create something. For example, an axe is the union of iron and the form of an axe. I once broke two separate axes attempting to chop down a tree. The specific axes were affected, but the form-of-an-axe, being a concept that exists outside of embodiment, was not. 



Now Plotinus is going to discuss the nature of this thing called "the Animate." As always, he gives us several possibilities:

 
Now this Animate might be merely the body as having life: it might be the Couplement of Soul and body: it might be a third and different entity formed from both.

The Animate could simply be the living body, or it could be the union or "Couplement" of Soul and Body, or it could be some third thing formed from both. Clear enough? The rest of the chapter is dedicated to considering the second two possibilities, starting with the "Couplement" of soul and body.

How could suffering, for example, be seated in this Couplement?

It may be suggested that some unwelcome state of the body produces a distress which reaches to a Sensitive-Faculty which in turn merges into Soul. But this account still leaves the origin of the sensation unexplained.




In other words, sensation may affect the soul. But we still haven't accounted for the existence of sensation.

Another suggestion might be that all is due to an opinion or judgement: some evil seems to have befallen the man or his belongings and this conviction sets up a state of trouble in the body and in the entire Animate. But this account leaves still a question as to the source and seat of the judgement: does it belong to the Soul or to the Couplement? Besides, the judgement that evil is present does not involve the feeling of grief: the judgement might very well arise and the grief by no means follow: one may think oneself slighted and yet not be angry; and the appetite is not necessarily excited by the thought of a pleasure. We are, thus, no nearer than before to any warrant for assigning these affections to the Couplement.

Is that clear? He's saying that we could suggest that "grief" or "pain" are just judgements. But who is it that has the judgment? Is it the Couplement or the Soul? And, furthermore, just the opinion that something is bad doesn't entail the actual feeling of the bad thing. I can read about a natural disaster on social media and judge, "That is bad," but that doesn't mean I actually have any experience of suffering over it. Therefore, the idea of suffering (or pleasure?) as a judgment doesn't allow us to say that it is the Couplement of Soul and body that actually experiences suffering or pleasure. 


Is it any explanation to say that desire is vested in a Faculty-of-desire and anger in the Irascible-Faculty, and, collectively, that all tendency is seated in the Appetitive-Faculty? Such a statement of the facts does not help towards making the affections common to the Couplement; they might still be seated either in the Soul alone or in the body alone. On the one hand if the appetite is to be stirred, as in the carnal passion, there must be a heating of the blood and the bile, a well-defined state of the body; on the other hand, the impulse towards The Good cannot be a joint affection, but, like certain others, too, it would necessarily belong to the Soul alone.

That is, certain affections are definitely bodily-- you can't have sex, or even want to have sex, without your body doing serious work. Therefore, some affections are bodily at least in part. On the other hand, "the impulse toward The Good" must belong only to the Soul. 

Now, why is that? Is this simply the prejudice of an era that was increasingly hostile toward physical matter? It's worth noting that at the time Plotinus is writing, virtually every religious system aims at getting away from embodiment in some way or another. Or is it a logical consequence of a metaphysical system in which concepts and ideals are seen as necessarily outside of physical embodiment? 

It's both getting ahead of ourselves and stretching my knowledge of this stuff almost to the breaking point to talk about The One, but it may help. In the same way that red objects participate in a higher principle called red or red-ness, everything that exists as a unity must receive its unity from an eternal principle called Unity, Oneness, or The One. A later author in the same tradition writes that the One "is truly the first, and it lacks nothing, nor does it need anything else with it except itself; it is the cause of all other things, and does not receive its qualities from another. It is not a material body, nor is it compounded of material bodies, nor is it mixed with anything other than itself, but rather is all things in itself. Therefore it may not be called anything except the One."*

Now, Plotinus and other Platonic thinkers identified The One with The Good. The One, as you can see from the description above, is not a body and it is not made up of bodies. Therefore, to seek the One is to go beyond the body. If the Good is identical with the One, then to seek the Good is to go beyond the body. Therefore, the impulse toward the Good is an affection which is not bodily, while the impulse to have sex is an affection which is bodily. Plotinus's conclusion follows:

Reason, then, does not permit us to assign all the affections to the Couplement.



And he elaborates on the complications:

In the case of carnal desire, it will certainly be the Man that desires, and yet, on the other-hand, there must be desire in the Desiring-Faculty as well. How can this be? Are we to suppose that, when the man originates the desire, the Desiring-Faculty moves to order? How could the Man have come to desire at all unless through a prior activity in the Desiring-Faculty? Then it is the Desiring-Faculty that takes the lead? Yet how, unless the body be first in the appropriate condition?

The question, then, is one commonly asked to this day. Are your experiences simply responses to bodily states? But if so, where do the impulses to move the body come from? 

Tune in next time, when maybe we'll find the answer!



*Picatrix Book 1 Ch 1, Greer and Warnock translation



Welcome back!

Last time, we looked at the second chapter of the first tractate of the first of Plotinus's Enneads. To recap, in that chapter, Plotinus talked about the soul, and wondered whether it was identical with something called Essential Soul. If that was true, it would mean that the Soul is an ideal form or eternal quality, unable to be affected by changes within time. And so, that would mean that the soul is not the seat of our sensory experience. But is this, in fact, the case? Let's read on and find out.

As always, keep in mind that I'm approaching this as an interested layman, and not anything resembling an expert in Plotinus, Neoplatonism, Ancient Greek philosophy, or anything else for that matter. If you'd like to follow along, the translation I'm using is online here. With that said, let's jump right into Ennead 1, Tracate 1, Chapter 3.

Plotinus starts by telling us that

We may treat of the Soul as in the body-- whether it be set above it or actually within it-- since the association of the two constitutes the one thing called the living organism, the Animate.

So, whether or not the Soul is truly within the body or not, we can treat it as if it were in the body, since the body and soul together are what make up a living thing, or Animate. (It's probably worth recalling that the word "anima" means "soul." "Animate" or "animated," then, would mean "ensouled." I don't read or speak Greek, but it seems likely enough that the translator is rendering a word which means "ensouled being" with the English word "Animate," capitalized to emphasize its importance.)

Now from this relation, from the Soul using the body as an instrument, it does not follow that the Soul must share the body's experiences: a man does not himself feel all the experiences of the tools with which he is working.

Okay, here is where I begin to become a little confused.

From my perspective, experience is something that I have-- my fingers contact the keyboard, and I perceive the shape and texture of the keys. I look out the window, and experience an image of the sidewalk outside the cafe where I'm writing. From this point of view, there are either two or three things involved in any experience. There is the sensory experience-- the image of the sidewalk, the feeling of the keyboard-- and there is the thing that has the experience. That's two.

On the other hand, I can close my eyes and picture the sidewalk in detail-- and then, if I like, I can add in all kinds of things that aren't there in the physical world, like a parade of stormtroopers lead by Great Cthulhu, all singing the Internationale. The Stormtooper Parade isn't there in the material world, but I can experience an image of it. The image can be shown to coincide with the movement of chemicals in my brain-- but it isn't a movement of chemicals in my brain, it's a parade of Stormtroopers led by Great Cthulhu singing the Internationale. Mental imagery, then, might be a third thing. Or, it might not be-- the fact is that the image of the sidewalk that I seem to perceive with my eyes is also a mental image, produced in my mind. So there may be only two types of things.

...From my perspective at least. But I'm not trying to understand how I already think about things-- I'm trying to understand how Plotinus thinks about things. For him, it doesn't necessarily follow that the Soul shares the body's experiences. He uses the image of a man using a tool. You can hit a nail with a hammer, but you don't experience the nail in the way the hammer does. The Soul may use the body in the same way-- and this must be the case, if the soul is an Ideal Form, existing beyond time and change.

Let's go on, though, and see what else Plotinus has to tell us.

It may be objected that the Soul must, however, have Sense-Perception, since its use of its instruments must acquaint it with the external conditions, and such knowledge comes by way of sense. Thus, it will be argued, the eyes are the instrument of seeing, and seeing may bring distress to the soul: hence the Soul may feel sorrow and pain and every other affection that belongs to the body; and from this again will spring desire, the Soul seeking the mending of its instrument.

If the Soul uses the body, then it must be able to perceive what the body perceives. And if this is the case, then the Soul might feel sorrow or distress when the body does. And from that, desire would come from the Soul "seeking to mend its instrument." Plotinus says that someone might propose this as an objection, and that seems straightforward enough to me. How is he going to get around it?

But, we ask, how, possibly, can these affections pass from body to Soul? Body may communicate qualities or conditions to another body: but-- body to Soul? Something happens to A; does that make it happen to B? As long as we have agent and instrument, there are two distinct entities; if the Soul uses the body it is separate from it.

I've got to tell you, I'm resisting Mr. Plotinus here very strongly. In his assertion that a body can't communicate qualities or conditions to another body, I'm reminded of half-remembered college lectures on Descartes and (rather worse) Patricia Churchland. The fact remains that we experience either all or most things via the body-- how can there be a "we" apart from this? 

I think the key to understanding what he means here is this: "As long as we have agent and instrument, there are two distinct entities." Is this necessarily the case? Why?

Since our goal is to try to understand what the old man is talking about, let's provisionally accept it for now. If the Soul is a distinct type of thing from the body, then it isn't affected by the body. I think, also, that we need to keep the ancient Greek metaphysics that I discussed in the last post in mind. If the body has a soul in the way that a red candle has redness, then the soul isn't affected by change in the body, anymore than the color red is affected by a red candle being burned up, thrown in the trash, or painted green.

As it turns out, Plotinus is going to address these issues now:

But apart from the philosophical separation how does Soul stand to body?

Clearly there is a combination. And for this several modes are possible. There might be a complete coalescence: Soul might be interwoven through the body: or it might be an Ideal-Form detached or an Ideal-Form in governing contact like a pilot: or there might be part of the Soul detached and another part in contact, the disjoined part being the agent or user, the conjoined part ranking with the instrument or thing used.

In order for the forgoing to work, we need to provisionally accept that the Soul cannot be affected by the body, for the reasons given. If this is the case, how do the Soul and the body relate? 

Plotinus answers, "by combination."

But what does this combination look like?

Here are the possibilities he gives:

1. A complete coalescence. In this case, I suppose, the Soul and body would indeed be blended into a whole.

2. The soul might be interwoven through the body. It's unclear how this is different from Option 1.

3. The Soul might be an Ideal Form, detached from the body.

4. The Soul might be an Ideal Form, governing the body as a pilot governs a ship.

5. Part of the Soul might be detached from the body, while the other part is in contact with it. If this is the case, the attached part would "rank with," or be on the level of, the body itself. 

Of these options, which seems most likely, at the outset? 

Plotinus concludes this section with the following, very interesting words:

In this last case it will be the double task of philosophy to direct this lower Soul towards the higher, the agent, and except in so far as the conjunction is absolutely necessary, to sever the agent from the instrument, the body, so that it need not forever have its Acts upon or through this inferior. 

It seems to me that there is a whole lot to unpack in this one sentence. 

First, remember that he's referring to the possibility that the Soul has separate parts-- one part attached to the body, the other separate from it. In that case, part of the soul acts as the agent, the thing that operates the body. The other part would then have to be the part that perceives what the body perceives. Importantly, this would include distress, sorrow, and suffering.  

Given this, he tells us, the task of philosophy will be to direct the lower Soul toward the higher. Now, this points to an idea which I've encountered before, which is that "philosophy" meant something different in ancient times than it does in ours. What Plotinus is talking about sounds, to me, more like a spiritual discipline than like a preoccupation of overpaid college professors. 

Another author,* writing some 7 or 800 years later, but in the same tradition, wrote, "He alone is perfect who attains the highest level of knowledge, and delights in and loves that level of knowledge. They were called 'philosophers' in Greek, and in Latin this word is properly interpreted 'lovers of knowledge.' Whoever does not strive for knowledge is defective and weak in authority, and therefore ought not to be called human, despite having the name, form, and figure of a human."

And so, the work of Philosophy, if the Soul has separate parts, is to unite the lower part of the Soul to the higher, and to detach it from the body as much as possible "so that it need not forever have its Acts upon or through this inferior.

How could that be, and what would that mean?













(*Picatrix Bk 1 Ch 6, Greer and Warnock translation.)



 Welcome back, and notice my handy new numbering system! This post will focus on the second chapter (if chapter is even the right term) of the  first tractate of the first Ennead.

As a reminder, when we last left Plotinus he told us that we were inquiring into just what it is that experiences "pleasure and distress, fear and courage, desire and aversion." Our options, remember, are "Soul," "Body," or a third thing which is either a blend of these two, or a real third thing arising from the blending. Firstly, said the man himself, we're going to have to figure out just what is the seat of sense-perception. As a reminder, the translation I'm working with is online here. In this translation, everything in [brackets] is a note added for clarity by the translator.

With that said, let's move on to Chapter 2...

....

"This first enquiry obliges us to consider at the outset the nature of the Soul-- that is whether a distinction is to be made between Soul and Essential Soul [between an individual soul and the Soul-Kind in itself.]"

(All Plotinus quotes in red... like how Jesus quotes are red in the Bible.)

Okay. Reading that, did you to think to yourself something like, "Well, I'm lost" or "Maybe it was insane to start with Plotinus" or "Do you think anyone will notice if I quietly close this book and run away"? 

If so, welcome to the club! 

At this point, it becomes clear (if it hasn't already) that Plotinus is living in a different mental universe from the one you and I inhabit. If I were to make my own inquiry into the nature of my consciousness (a word which is itself loaded with all kinds of presuppositions), it would never occur to me to ask whether my mind is distinguishable from mind-stuff in general, or mind-kind as a whole. But as near as I can tell, that's exactly what Plotinus wants to ask about the thing he's calling "soul." 

(A note in another translation that I looked at references a couple of chapters of Aristotle's Metaphysics here. I've looked at the relevant chapters, and decided that to jump right into the middle of Aristotle at the same time as I'm working on Plotinus will probably make me insane, so I'm going to leave it aside for right now.) 

Next:

If such a distinction holds, then the soul [in man] is some sort of a composite and at once we may agree that it is a recipient and-- if only reason allows--- that all the affections and experiences really have their seat in the Soul, and with the affections every state and mood, good and bad alike.

This is one sentence, and yet there is so much here. Okay, to break this down, I'm going to have to take a stab at explaining ancient Greek metaphysics, which is a subject I half understand at best. As I understand it, the theory of forms is as follows:

The quotes from Plotinus are in red. The book on my shelf is red. The bulbs on the Christmas tree are red. The candle next to the tree is red.

In order for all these disparate things to share the quality "red," there must be some thing called "red" which exists prior to the tree, the book, and the candle being red. (This is part of what leads to the idea of the One-- in order for anything to have unity, Unity itself must have existence.)

If I understand Plotinus correctly, then, he's asking the question, whether you and I have souls in the same way that my book, my Christmas tree and my candle have redness-- or whether our souls are essential forms, like redness itself. So, do you have a soul, or do you have Soul?

If you have a soul, he says, then it is necessarily a composite. Why would that be? I suppose, because if this is the case, then "You have a soul" is the same sort of sentence as "The candle is red." The candle is red because it is a composite of different sorts of things, including redness, candle-ness, and so on.

And, if that's the case, then the soul can have affections and experiences. Why? Here the answer, I think, is this: The red candle can change. It can be lit, be burnt out, be broken or thrown in the trash. But the essential thing, "Red," never changes. It is a permanent quality or essence, existing beyond time. If your soul is also a permanent essence, existing beyond time, then it can't change-- and so it can't have experiences.

What do you think, Plotinus? Did I get that one right?

But if Soul [in man] and Essential Soul are one and the same, then the Soul will be an Ideal-Form unperceptive of all those activities which it imparts to another Kind but possessing within itself that native Act of its own which Reason manifests.

I think the answer is "Yes." If the Soul is the same as Essential Soul, then it won't be changed by experiences and affections, anymore than Redness is changed by burning a red candle. 

I want to set this clause aside for right now:  "but possessing within itself that native Act of its own which Reason manifests." ...and come back to it in a bit. 

If this be so, then, indeed, we may think of the Soul as an immortal-- if the immortal, the imperishable, must be impassive, giving out something of itself but taking nothing from without except for what it receives from the Existents prior to itself from which Existents, in that they are nobler, it cannot be sundered.

So: If the soul is a quality like redness, it is immortal, in the same way that redness is immortal. And it will be incapable of experience or change. Instead, those things which participate in it will receive it as a quality. And, interestingly, it can receive-- but only from "Existents" prior to it. What does that mean? Prior to "red," there is "color." Red, Blue, Purple, and Magenta all possess Color, which is an "Existent" prior to them all. What Existents are prior to Soul?

Plotinus goes on:

Now what could bring fear to a nature thus unreceptive of all the outer? Fear demands feeling. Nor is there place for courage: courage implies the presence of danger. And such desires as are satisfied by the filling or voiding of the body, must be proper to something very different from the Soul, to that only which admits of replenishment and voidance.
 
This is what we've been saying: If the soul is the same as Essential Soul, then it doesn't experience change in time.

And how could the Soul lend itself to any admixture? An essential is not mixed. Or of the intrusion of anything alien? If it did, it would be seeking the destruction of its own nature. Pain must be equally far from it. And Grief-- how or for what could it grieve? Whatever possesses Existence is supremely free, dwelling, unchangeable, within its own peculiar nature. And can any increase bring joy, where nothing, not even anything good, can accrue? What such an Existent is, it is, unchangeably.

More of the same, but notice that the translator chose to capitalize the word "Existence." This emphasizes that, in the Platonic tradition as I understand it, permanent qualities like red, like Plotinus seems to be assuming the Soul to be, have more reality than the changing phenomena of everyday life.

Thus assuredly Sense-Perception, Discursive-Reasoning and all our ordinary mentation are foreign to the Soul: for senseation is a receiving-- whether of an Ideal-Form or of an impassive body-- and reasoning and all ordinary mental action deal with sensation.

Okay. All of this follows from the premise, "Soul in man is an Ideal Form." But did you see the part where he demonstrated that to be the case? Or is he simply working with it as an assumption? 

Coming up: 

The question still remains to be examined in the matter of the intellections-- whether these are to be assigned to the Soul-- and as to Pure-Pleasure, whether this belongs to the Soul in its solitary state."


Plotinus 1

Dec. 5th, 2019 12:07 pm
I've decided to begin re-start proper with Plotinus. 

Who Was Plotinus?

Plotinus "is generally regarded as the founder of Neoplatonism. He is one of the most influential philosophers in antiquity after Plato and Aristotle." I got that from The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. I'm interested in Plotinus because Neoplatonism is the foundation of the Western magical tradition. From Picatrix to the Golden Dawn, if you're working with Western esoteric philosophy, you're working with Neoplatonism. 

...And therein lies the trouble, for me, because Neoplatonism is damned hard to understand!

Why Start Here?

I've had Plotinus's Enneads on my shelf for some time. The book is almost at eye-level, and I can see the title out of the corner of my eye.

Mocking me.

The thing is... Plotinus is hard. I mean really hard. I've made several attempts at the Enneads, and I've always slunk away in failure. So now I'm going to make another attempt. Right here, in public. Why? I'm not sure, but there are two possible reasons:

1. I love to suffer.

2. I'm hoping that someone who is smarter than me will wander in here, see me flailing about trying to understand this stuff, and explain to me why I'm wrong!

With all that said, let's start with 
  • The Enneads
  • The First Ennead
  • First Tractate
  • Chapter 1

(Yeah, we're taking this one slowly. If you'd like to follow along, the translation I'm using is online here.)
 
"Pleasure and distress," opens Plotinus, "fear and courage, desire and aversion, where have these affections and experiences their seat? Clearly, either in the Soul alone, or in the Soul as employing the body, or in some third entity deriving from both.

And for this third entity, again, there are two possible modes: it might be either a blend, or a distinct form due to the blending."

And so we begin. Our subject, then-- apparently-- is a question. Where do experiences happen? Is it in the body, or the soul, or some third thing? And, if a third thing, is it a mix of body and soul, or a true third thing arising from that mixing?

For what it's worth, I am coming to Plotinus with my own answer to this question. Or, rather, with several answers, one of which I came to on my own, and the others of which I've learned. What Plotinus's own answer is, I have no idea. So let's go on and find out!

He tells us next, "what applies to the affections applies to whatsoever acts, physical or mental, spring from them."

What does this mean?

Well. He has listed "courage" as one of the affections. Suppose I am possessed of courage in a particular setting. I'm hiking in the woods with my family, and we see a mountain lion on the trail. Instead of running away, though, I raise my arms and scream and run toward the mountain lion. In my mind, I am thinking, "I want to protect my family;" in the material world, I'm running toward the lion, screaming and flailing. These are mental and physical acts. So, for Plotinus, these acts, then, are rooted in whichever of the three possible locations the affections have their seat. 

Or is that what he's saying?

Because he next tells us that "We have to examine discursive reason and the ordinary mental action upon objects of sense, and enquire whether these have the one seat with the affections and experiences, or perhaps sometimes the one seat, sometimes another."

So it may be the case that mentation has a different source than affection, at least sometimes. 

"And we must consider also our acts of Intellection, their mode and their seat. 

And this very examining principle, which investigates and decides in these matters, must be brought to light.

Firstly, what is the seat of Sense-Perception? This is the obvious beginning, since the affections and experiences either are sensations of some kind or at least never occur apart from sensation."

So we have a whole bunch of different terms that we're looking at in this work. And each of these terms is a different state of being, that we all experience, including:

Affection (meaning a disposition like pleasure, fear, or desire.)
Experience
Mental action
Physical action
Sensation
The very capacity to observe, act, and decide

To return to what we said before, Plotinus's goal is to discover where these things "have their seat." And our four possibilities are: The Soul, the Body, A Mix of the Two, A Third Thing Resulting from the Mix of the Two. 

Concluding

...And that's all for now. Like I said, I'm taking Plotinus very, very slowly.

I'm finding that just by the act of reading and breaking down this little bit, I understand this work better than I ever have. I'm serious; I've read this first page a half-dozen times before now without figuring out what Plotinus is even talking about. But now I understand-- or I think I do; maybe that guy who's a lot smarter than me that I mentioned above will come in here and tell me I'm wrong. But if I'm right, Plotinus is starting with what is, to my mind, the most interesting philosophical question of all: The question of experience. What is this thing that, when electricity and chemicals move through neurons in the brain, sees the color "red"? 

Come back next time, and maybe we'll find out!

Profile

readoldthings

December 2024

S M T W T F S
1234567
891011121314
1516 17 18192021
22232425262728
293031    

Syndicate

RSS Atom

Most Popular Tags

Style Credit

Expand Cut Tags

No cut tags
Page generated Jun. 27th, 2025 03:49 am
Powered by Dreamwidth Studios